IS INTELLIGENT
DESIGN A FORM OF NATURAL THEOLOGY?
By William A.
Dembski
There are good and
bad reasons to be skeptical of intelligent design. Perhaps the best reason is
that intelligent design has yet to establish itself as a thriving scientific
research program. Thus far philosophical, theoretical, and foundational
concerns have tended to predominate. From the vantage of design advocates, this
simply reflects the earliness of the hour and the need to clear the decks
before a shift of paradigms can take place. Give us more time, and we'll
deliver on the program. That's our promise. Skeptics are at this point in their
rights to refuse such promissory notes, albeit without sabotaging our efforts
to make good on this promise.
Besides good reasons
for being skeptical of intelligent design, there are also bad reasons. I list
about ten in the appendix of my book _Intelligent Design_ (InterVarsity, 1999)
and another ten or so in the final chapter of my forthcoming book _No Free
Lunch_ (Rowman & Littlefield, 2001). One bad reason I've touched on but
haven't addressed at length in either of these books is the charge that
intelligent design is a form of natural theology. These days within the
science-religion community, natural theology tends to be viewed as a
disreputable enterprise that hearkens back to pre-Darwinian days and is now thoroughly
passˇ. While I regard this judgment as unduly harsh, I also regard it as
irrelevant to intelligent design. Intelligent design is not a form of natural
theology.
Not everyone agrees.
Ian Barbour is a prominent case in point. In speaking before the American
Academy of Religion regarding Huston Smith's doubts about evolutionary theory,
Barbour directed the following criticism at intelligent design:
"Philosophical proponents of intelligent design, such as William Dembski
and Stephen Meyer, write in the tradition of natural theology in which science
is used as evidence of the existence of a designer. My own approach is not
natural theology but a theology of nature in which one asks how nature as
understood by science is related to the divine as understood from the religious
experience of a historical community." (Metaviews 099, 30 November 2000;
talk originally presented at the American Academy of Religion, Nashville, 19
November 2000.)
In this essay I'm
going to argue that intelligent design is not a form of natural theology.
What's more, I'm going to argue that Barbour's theology of nature, as he calls
it, is itself a form of natural theology, though the theology in this case is
not traditional theism but the panentheism of process theology. First let's
turn to the charge that intelligent design is a form of natural theology. To be
fair to Barbour, he does not say that my colleagues and I are actually doing
natural theology. Rather, he says that we write in the tradition of natural
theology. He therefore seems to allow that we are not committing the exact same
mistakes (if in fact they were mistakes) as natural theologians of the past. On
the other hand, in saying that we write in the tradition of natural theology,
he suggests that our aims are substantially those of the old natural
theologians.
I submit that
intelligent design isn't doing natural theology. What's more, I submit that
whatever intelligent design is doing, its aims are substantially different from
those of natural theology. To see this, consider the last major push of natural
theology prior to the publication of Darwin's _Origin of Species_. I have in
mind here the eight Bridgewater treatises. The Rev. Francis Henry Egerton,
eighth and last Earl of Bridgewater, died in 1829. At the time of his death he
directed that £8,000 be used by the president of the Royal Society of London to
publish works on "the Power, Wisdom and Goodness of God as manifested in
the Creation illustrating such work by all reasonable arguments as, for
instance, the variety and formation of God's creatures, in the animal,
vegetable and mineral kingdoms; the effect of digestion and thereby of
conversion; the construction of the hand of man and an infinite variety of
other arguments; as also by discoveries ancient and modern in arts, sciences,
and the whole extent of modern literature."
This passage from
Lord Bridgewater's bequest captures perfectly the spirit of natural theology.
Natural theology was primarily in the business of identifying and expatiating
on features of the natural world that provided independent evidence of what
revealed or sacred theology already knew about God, namely, that God is
powerful, wise, and good. The titles of the eight Bridgewater treatises
indicate this as well: (1) _The Adaptation of External Nature to the Moral and
Intellectual Constitution of Man_, by Thomas Chalmers (1833); (2) _Chemistry,
Meteorology, and Digestion_, by William Prout, (1834); (3) _History, Habits,
and Instincts of Animals_, by William Kirby (1835); (4) _The Hand, as Evincing
Design_, by Sir Charles Bell (1837); (5) _Geology and Mineralogy_, by Dean
Buckland (1837); (6) _The Adaptation of External Nature to the Physical
Condition of Man_, by J. Kidd, (1837); (7) _Astronomy and General Physics_, by
William Whewell (1839), (8) _Animal and Vegetable Physiology_, by P. M. Roget
(1840).
The stereotypical
argument of a natural theologian begins with "Isn't it amazing how
...." The natural theologian then fills in the blank with some feature of
the natural world that inspires admiration and argues how this feature, once
properly interpreted, demonstrates the manifold wisdom, power, and goodness of
God. The problem with such arguments, of course, is that they can be turned on
their head. Thus for every instance where the natural theologian finds reason
to sing God's praises, the natural anti-theologian finds reason to lament
nature's cruelty. Darwin, for instance, thought there was "too much misery
in the world" to find solace in natural theology: "I cannot persuade
myself that a beneficent and omnipotent God would have designedly created the
Ichneumonidae with the express intention of their feeding within the living
bodies of Caterpillars, or that a cat should play with mice." Other
examples he pointed to included "ants making slaves" and "the
young cuckoo ejecting its foster-brother."
The impulse to
natural theology remains alive to this day, though it's particular expressions
have changed. These days, instead of looking to some particular feature of the
world located at a specific place and time (e.g., the human hand, the mammalian
eye, or some other biological contrivance), contemporary natural theologians
tend to look to global features of the natural world. Thus Michael Corey will
look to the laws of physics and the fine-tuning of cosmological constants and
therewith draw inferences about the attributes of God (cf. his forthcoming _The
God Hypothesis: Discovering Design in Our "Just Right" Goldilocks
Universe_ with Rowman & Littlefield). Or consider Michael Denton's
_Nature's Destiny: How the Laws of Biology Reveal Purpose in the Universe_
(Free Press, 1998). In that book Denton considers the highly specific
conditions that needed to be satisfied in our solar system and on the earth in
particular for intelligent life like ours to form. From these considerations
Denton concludes that there is a grand purpose behind the natural world.
Denton and
Corey are happy to identify themselves
as doing natural theology. Other thinkers, especially those influenced by
process theology, though perhaps disavowing that label, are nonetheless
properly viewed as engaged in natural theology as well. To see this, consider
the locus classicus of natural theology, namely William Paley's _Natural
Theology_, subtitled _Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity,
Collected from the Appearances of Nature_. The subtitle is revealing. Paley's
project was to examine features of the natural world ("appearances of
nature") and therewith draw conclusions about a designing intelligence responsible
for those features (whom Paley identified with the God of Christianity).
The impulse to
natural theology is always this: To look at some aspect of the natural world
and therewith draw conclusions about some reality that extends beyond the
natural world. This impulse is anti-reductionist. Thus instead of seeing nature
built from the ground up of mindless elementary constituents that come together
through equally mindless forces, the contemporary natural theologian argues
that a top-down purposiveness is intrinsic to a proper understanding of the
world. Contemporary natural theologians point to the very existence of the
world, the laws by which the world operates, the capacity of the world to
organize itself, the intelligibility of the world, and the unreasonable
effectiveness of mathematics for comprehending the world as questions that
nature raises but that also point beyond nature.
In this respect
Arthur Peacocke, John Polkinghorne, and Ian Barbour are as much engaged in
natural theology as any natural theologians of time past. Peacocke, for
instance, is much taken with Charles Kingsley's children's book _The Water
Babies_, in which nature is described as "making things that make
themselves." This self-organizational co-creating feature of the natural
world is for Peacocke unaccountable except in theological terms whereby God
becomes the source of being for the world. What's more, on the basis of what
contemporary science teaches about the natural world, Peacocke is as quick to
ascribe attributes to God as any of the British natural theologians of old. To
be sure, Peacocke's list of attributes differs significantly from the lists of
earlier natural theologians, who were seeking to underwrite traditional
Christian theism. Peacocke has little use for traditional Christian theism,
with its outdated (at least from his perspective) view of miracles and divine
perfections. For instance, on the basis of contingency in both quantum physics
and evolutionary biology, Peacocke rejects the idea that God knows future events.
For Peacocke the future is simply not there to be known. Our best science
doesn't allow it, and so theology must follow lock step. This is natural
theology. Moreover, unlike natural theology prior to Darwin, this is natural
theology unconstrained by revealed theology.
I want now return to
the question that motivated this essay in the first place: Is intelligent
design a form of natural theology? If intelligent design were a form of natural
theology, then intelligent design should be looking at certain features of the
natural world and therewith drawing conclusions about some reality that extends
beyond the natural world. Is intelligent design doing that? I submit it is not.
The fundamental idea that animates intelligent design is that events, objects, and
structures in the world can exhibit features that reliably signal the effects
of intelligence. Disciplines as diverse as animal learning and behavior,
forensics, archeology, cryptography, and the search for extraterrestrial
intelligence thus all fall within intelligent design.
Intelligent design
becomes controversial when methods developed in special sciences (like
forensics and archeology) for sifting the effects of intelligence from natural
causes get applied to natural systems where no reified, evolved, or embodied
intelligence is likely to have been involved. What if the methods for
identifying intelligence tell us that Michael Behe's irreducibly complex
biochemical machines are in fact designed? What if careful analysis of such
systems shows that natural causes (like the Darwinian mechanism of natural
selection and random variation) are in principle incapable of generating such
systems? In that case to charge intelligent design with trading in arguments
from ignorance or invoking a god-of-the-gaps is no longer tenable. In that case
gaps in naturalistic explanations for such systems are not gaps of ignorance
about underlying natural causes but rather gaps in the very structure of
physical reality.
The idea that nature
is a closed system of natural causes and that natural causes provide a complete
account of everything that occurs in nature is deeply entrenched in the West
and in its current incarnation is most directly traceable to Spinoza (within
liberal Christian theology its fountainhead is Friedrich Schleiermacher).
Nevertheless, the idea that natural causes are complete has no more warrant
than that mathematics should be complete in the sense that every true
mathematical claim should be deducible from a simple set of axioms. G?del
effectively demolished the latter misconception. Intelligent design is
challenging the former. Moreover, it is challenging the former by pointing to
phenomena in nature that nature is in principle incapable of accounting for
strictly in terms of natural causes.
In arguing that
naturalistic explanations are incomplete or equivalently that natural causes
cannot account for certain features of the natural world, I am placing natural
causes in contradistinction to intelligent causes. The scientific community has
itself drawn this distinction in its use of these twin categories of causation.
Thus Francisco Ayala writes, "Darwin's greatest accomplishment [was] to
show that the directive organization of living beings can be explained as the
result of a natural process, natural selection, without any need to resort to a
Creator or other external agent [read 'design']." Natural causes, as the
scientific community understands them, are causes that operate according to
deterministic and non-deterministic laws and that can be characterized in terms
of chance, necessity, or their combination (cf. Jacques Monod's _Chance and
Necessity_). To be sure, if one is more liberal about what one means by natural
causes, and includes among natural causes telic processes that are not
reducible to chance and necessity (like the ancient Stoics did by endowing
nature with immanent teleology), then the claim that natural causes are
incomplete dissolves. But that is not how the scientific community understands
natural causes.
The distinction
between natural and intelligent causes now raises an interesting question when
it comes to embodied intelligences like us, who are at once physical systems
and intelligent agents: Are embodied intelligences natural causes? Even if the
actions of an embodied intelligence proceed solely by natural causes, being
determined entirely by the constitution and dynamics of the physical system
that embodies it, that does not mean the origin of that system can be explained
by reference solely to natural causes. Such systems could exhibit derived
intentionality in which the underlying source of intentionality remains
irreducible to natural causes. A fundamental tenet of intelligent design is
that intelligent agency, even when conditioned by a physical system that
embodies it, cannot be reduced to natural causes without remainder. Within the
intelligent design literature that remainder is typically identified as some
form of complexity ("irreducibly complexity" for Michael Behe,
"functional complexity" for Marcel Sch?tzenberger, and "
specified complexity" in my case).
Design has had a
turbulent intellectual history. The chief difficulty with design to date has
consisted in discovering a conceptually powerful formulation of it that will
fruitfully advance science. While I fully grant that the history of design
arguments warrants misgivings, they do not apply to intelligent design. The
theory of intelligent design as my colleagues and I envision it is not an
atavistic return to the design arguments of William Paley and the Bridgewater
Treatises. William Paley was in no position to formulate the conceptual
framework for design that is now being developed. This new framework depends on
advances in probability theory, computer science, the concept of information,
molecular biology, and the philosophy of science -- to name but a few. Within
this framework design promises to become an effective conceptual tool for
investigating and understanding the natural world.
Increased
philosophical and scientific sophistication, however, is not alone in
separating our approach to design from Paley's. Paley's approach was closely
linked to his prior religious and metaphysical commitments. Ours is not.
Paley's designer was nothing short of the triune God of Christianity, a transcendent,
personal, moral being with all the perfections commonly attributed to this God.
On the other hand, the designer that emerges from a theory of intelligent
design is an intelligence capable of originating the complexity and specificity
that we find throughout the cosmos and especially in biological systems.
Persons with theological commitments can co-opt this designer and identify this
designer with the object of their worship. But this move is strictly optional
as far as the actual science of intelligent design is concerned.
The crucial question
for science is whether design helps us understand the world, and especially the
biological world, better than we do now when we systematically eschew
teleological notions from our scientific theorizing. Thus a scientist may view
design and its appeal to a designer as simply a fruitful device for
understanding the world, not attaching any special significance to questions
like whether a theory of design is in some ultimate sense true or whether the
designer actually exists. Philosophers of science would call this a
"constructive empiricist" approach to design. Scientists in the
business of manufacturing theoretical entities like quarks, strings, and cold
dark matter could therefore view the designer as just one more theoretical
entity to be added to the list. I follow here Ludwig Wittgenstein, who wrote:
"What a Copernicus or a Darwin really achieved was not the discovery of a
true theory but of a fertile new point of view." If design cannot be made
into a fertile new point of view that inspires exciting new areas of scientific
investigation, then it deserves to wither and die. Yet before that happens, it
deserves a fair chance to succeed.
We are now in a
position to see how intelligent design parts company with natural theology. Ian
Barbour claims that my colleagues and I are in the business of using scientific
evidence to establish the existence of a designer. And presumably once we've
established the existence of a designer, then we'll want to expatiate on the
attributes of that designer. If Barbour's characterization of our enterprise
were correct, then the charge that intelligent design is a form of natural
theology would stand. But that's not what we're about. Barbour has the logic of
intelligent design backwards. That logic does not move from features of the
world to proof of the existence of a designer to cataloguing attributes of the
designer. Rather, intelligent design begins with features of the world that are
inherently inexplicable in terms of natural causes -- not merely features of
the world that for now lack a natural-cause explanation but rather for which
natural causes are in principle incapable of providing an explanation (for
instance, in my writings I argue that the specified complexity of certain
biological systems constitutes such a feature). Next, intelligent design notes
that in our ordinary experience, when objects whose causal story we know
exhibit such features, then a designer was crucially involved in the object's
causal history.
It's at this point
that intelligent design could be co-opted into doing natural theology,
proclaiming that natural objects exhibiting such features establish the
existence of a designer. But intelligent design resists that temptation.
Instead of arguing for the existence of a designer (and thus formulating a
revamped design argument), intelligent design asks how positing an intelligent
cause to explain such objects offers fresh scientific insights. The designer of
intelligent design is not the God of any particular religious faith and not the
God of any particular philosophical reflection but merely a generic intelligent
cause capable of originating certain features of the natural world. Positing
such a designer to account for certain types of biological complexity is like
positing quarks to account for certain properties of subatomic particles. The
point is to see what a designer helps explain; the point is not to establish
the existence of the designer.
Granted, many of my
colleagues in the intelligent design movement are Christians and believe on
independent theological grounds in a designer qua God. But some, like Todd
Moody, are agnostics who are perfectly content investigating design in nature,
reject the sufficiency of undirected natural causes to account for that design,
but also avoid making any ontological commitments about a designer. To be sure,
intelligent design provides ready fodder for natural theology. Thus it's
understandable why critics of intelligent design are eager to conflate it with
natural theology. But intelligent design's connections with natural theology
are peripheral. Unless and until intelligent design can be made to succeed as a
scientific research program, there can be no talk of developing a natural
theology from it. And even if intelligent design succeeds as a scientific
research program, developing a natural theology from it is purely optional.
Indeed, when I
consider my own motivation and that of my colleagues in the intelligent design
movement, the traditional concerns of natural theology seem largely irrelevant.
Our motivation is certainly not to offer yet another argument for the existence
of God. Instead, our motivation is to explore some fascinating possibilities
for science and create room for that exploration to proceed unfettered. The
subtitle of Richard Dawkins's _The Blind Watchmaker_ reads _Why the Evidence of
Evolution Reveals a Universe Without Design_. Dawkins may in the end prove
right about design being absent from the universe. But design theorists insist
that science needs to address not only the evidence that reveals the universe
to be without design but also the evidence that reveals the universe to be with
design. Evidence is a two-edged sword: Claims capable of being refuted by
evidence are also capable of being supported by evidence. Even if design ends
up being rejected as an unfruitful explanatory tool for science, such a
negative outcome for design needs to result from the evidence for and against
design being fairly considered. Darwin himself would have agreed. At the very
start of the _Origin_ he wrote, "A fair result can be obtained only by
fully stating and balancing the facts and arguments on both sides of each
question." Consequently, any rejection of design must not result from
imposing arbitrary constraints on science that rule out design prior to any
consideration of evidence.
Two main such
constraints have historically been used to keep design outside the natural
sciences: methodological naturalism and dysteleology. According to
methodological naturalism, in explaining any natural phenomenon the natural
sciences are properly permitted to invoke only natural causes to the exclusion
of intelligent causes. Methodological naturalism is a regulative principle that
purports to keep science on the straight and narrow by limiting science to
natural causes. In fact it does nothing of the sort but constitutes a
straitjacket that actively impedes the progress of science. If an intelligence
actually did play a crucial role in the origin of biological complexity,
methodological naturalism would ensure that we could never know it. Imagine a
detective absolutely committed to explaining by natural causes why Frank's
corpse has a knife through the heart and the words "Die, Frank, Die!"
etched on his chest. Methodological naturalism requires the same unthinking
commitment from science.
The other constraint
for excluding design from science is dysteleology. Dysteleology refers to
inferior design -- typically design that is either evil or incompetent.
Dysteleology rules out design from the natural sciences on account of the
inferior design that nature is said to exhibit. Dysteleology might present a
problem if all design in nature were wicked or incompetent. But that's not the
case. To be sure, there are microbes that look designed to do a number on the
mammalian nervous system and biological structures that look cobbled together
by a long trial-and-error evolutionary process. But there are also biological
examples of nano-engineering that surpass anything human engineers have
concocted or entertain hopes of concocting. Dysteleology is primarily a
theological problem. To exclude design from biology simply because not all
examples of biological design live up to our expectations of what a designer
should or should not have done is an evasion. The problem of design in biology
is real and pervasive, and needs to be addressed head on and not sidestepped
because our presuppositions about design happen to rule out imperfect design.
Nature is a mixed bag. It is not William Paley's happy world of everything in
delicate harmony and balance. It is not the widely caricatured Darwinian world
of nature red in tooth and claw. Nature contains evil design, jerry-built
design, and exquisite design. Science needs to come to terms with design as
such and not dismiss it in the name of dysteleology.
A possible
terminological confusion over the phrase "intelligent design" needs
now to be cleared up. The confusion centers on what the adjective
"intelligent" is doing in the phrase "intelligent design."
"Intelligent" can mean nothing more than being the result of an
intelligent agent, even one who acts stupidly. On the other hand, it can mean
that an intelligent agent acted with consummate skill and mastery. Critics of
intelligent design often understand the "intelligent" in
"intelligent design" in the latter sense, and thus presume that
intelligent design must entail optimal design (and therefore a program of
natural theology). The intelligent design community, on the other hand,
understands the "intelligent" in "intelligent design"
simply to refer to intelligent agency (irrespective of skill, mastery, or
cleverness) and thus separates intelligent design from optimality of design.
But why then place
the adjective "intelligent" in front of the noun "design"?
Doesn't design already include the idea of intelligent agency, so that
juxtaposing the two becomes redundant? Redundancy is avoided because
intelligent design needs also to be distinguished from apparent design. Because
design in biology is so often attributed to natural forces (e.g., natural
selection), putting "intelligent" in front of "design"
ensures that the design we are talking about is not merely apparent but actual
(for scientific realists, actual in the sense that there is a real designer
behind the design; for scientific anti-realists, actual in the sense that the
design is in principle irreducible to natural causes). Whether the intelligence
thus posited acts cleverly or stupidly, wisely or unwisely, optimally or
suboptimally are separate questions.
At this point
critics of intelligent design often protest that design theorists have yet to
provide a careful definition of intelligence. While I agree that terms need to
be defined as carefully as possible, the call for definition can itself become
a subterfuge. Thus the call for definition can become a way of avoiding the
challenge posed by an idea by endlessly requiring further clarification of key
terms. The later Wittgenstein certainly thought the call for definition was
overrated. Indeed, the finiteness of language itself implies that the call for
definition must at some point either end or issue in circularity. Within
intelligent design, intelligence is a primitive notion much as force or energy
are primitive notions within physics. We can say intelligible things about
these notions and show how they can be usefully employed in certain contexts.
But in defining them, we gain no substantive insight.
The very word
intelligence derives from the Latin words "inter" (a preposition
meaning "between") and "lego" (a verb meaning to
"choose" or "select"). Thus strictly speaking intelligence
refers to the capacity to choose or select. Yet unlike natural selection, which
operates without goals or purposes, ordinarily when we think of an intelligence
as choosing or selecting, it is with a goal or purpose in mind. We could
therefore define intelligence as the capacity for rational or purposive or
deliberate or premeditated choice. Have we therefore defined intelligence to
the satisfaction of the critics of intelligent design? Hardly. When Howard Van
Till, for instance, issues his call for definition, his worry is not what
intelligence or design means as such, but what these terms mean in contexts
where no embodied intelligence was acting and thus where his view of nature as
a complete system of natural causes (cf. his fully gifted creation and robust
formational economy) comes under pressure. Invariably I've found that the call
to define intelligence by critics of intelligent design is not a call for clarification
but a defensive move to relieve pressure from some aspect of the critic's own
worldview that intelligent design calls into question.
From the foregoing
description of intelligent design it's clear that intelligent design is not a
form of natural theology. Natural theology attempts to answer theological and
metaphysical questions on the basis of what the science of the day is saying about
nature. Intelligent design, on the other hand, is simply interested in seeing
whether any interesting science can be done once it is found that certain
natural systems bear marks that in other contexts reliably signal the effects
of intelligence. Ian Barbour is therefore mistaken when he claims that Stephen
Meyer and I "write in the tradition of natural theology in which science
is used as evidence of the existence of a designer." We are not employing
science as evidence for the existence of a designer. We are merely trying to
rehabilitate design as a fruitful concept for science.
Skeptics like
Michael Shermer will regard this characterization of intelligent design as
disingenuous. As he kept repeating at last summer's _Design and Its Critics_
conference (Concordia University, Mequon, Wisconsin, 22-24 June 2000), "We
all know who you mean by the designer." Thus according to Shermer, even
though design theorists advertise that they are merely proposing a generic
designer, in fact they intend the Christian God in all his glory. This for
Shermer is enough to vitiate intelligent design as an intellectual project. As
far as he is concerned to destroy the program's credibility it is enough that
many design theorists are Christians who privately identify the designer coming
out of intelligent design as the God of their religious faith. In so arguing,
Shermer commits an obvious fallacy. The source or motivation for an idea does
not ultimately determine its merit, which must be assessed on its own terms if
it is to be assessed at all (to claim otherwise, as Shermer does, is to commit
what philosophers call the genetic fallacy).
Do we really want to
play the motivations game? If so, let's turn the tables. Does Shermer, for
instance, as a protegˇ of Stephen Jay Gould, likewise regard Gould's ideas
about evolution as in any way undermined because of Gould's philosophical and
political views? Should the fact that Gould's philosophical views about
contingency influence his evolutionary theorizing be enough to overthrow his
evolutionary theorizing? Should Gould's views on religion, in which he rejects
all religious belief that is not reducible to ethics and subjective experience,
count against his scientific views? Gould explicitly rejects that humanity is
made in the image of a beneficent God and attributes that realization to Darwin
(cf. his _Ever Since Darwin_). But such theological (or anti-theological)
claims are properly speaking beyond the remit of science. Do Gould's
extra-scientific views vitiate his scientific views? If not (and I agree that
they should not), then why should design theorists be held to a different
standard? Each of us has motives for doing the things that we do, and in very
few instances are those motives entirely pure or defensible. So what. The biographies
of the great scientists of the past hardly read like hagiography.
Intelligent design
may for the time being be operated mainly by Christians. But it is not owned by
Christians. It is not even owned by theists. Thomas Aquinas, writing in the
_Summa Contra Gentiles_, remarked, "For seeing that natural things run
their course according to a fixed order, and since there cannot be order
without a cause of order, men, for the most part, perceive that there is one
who orders the things that we see. But who or of what kind this cause of order
may be, or whether there be but one, cannot be gathered from this general
consideration." Leaving aside whether Thomas's argument from order to a
cause of order is sound, it's clear that just what that cause of order is, is
almost wholly unspecified for Thomas and can only be given definite content by
recourse to theology and metaphysics. Indeed, for Thomas the "cause of
order" that we infer strictly from reflection on the natural order does
not even issue in a generic monotheism.
In my own
experience, I've found acceptance of my work on intelligent design from theists
of all stripes. I've also had Hindu believers congratulate me for my work on
intelligent design. Intelligent design sits well with Jungian psychology, stoicism,
and Neoplatonism. Just about anyone who takes teleology seriously and refuses
the reductive naturalism of contemporary science finds intelligent design
congenial. Intelligent design is not in the business of filling in the details
of who or what the designer is. That's a task for theology and metaphysics.
Michael Shermer, Eugenie Scott, and their supporters think science will suffer
irreparable harm if intelligent design proves successful and thus would like
the public to believe that intelligent design is a theological enterprise. As a
consequence, they keep their propaganda mills busy issuing the appropriate
denials, disinformation, and damage control.
Intelligent design
has theological implications, but that does not make it a theological enterprise.
The truth is that intelligent design is a fledgling scientific research program
that wants to demonstrate its merits fair and square in the scientific world --
without appealing to religious authority but also without having constantly to
defend itself against willful misrepresentations. Often when I write and speak
about intelligent design and then step back to reflect on the vituperation my
work receives, I'm reminded of those Kafka short stories where some hapless
figure is tied up and smothered in endless bureaucratic red tape. The
fundamental claim of intelligent design is straightforward and easily
intelligible, namely, there are natural systems that are in principle incapable
of being explained in terms of natural causes and that exhibit features that in
any other circumstance we would attribute to intelligence. That claim can be
considered on its own merits. Let's look at some actual systems and do the
analysis. Science is filled with proscriptive generalizations about things that
can't happen. Do such proscriptive claims apply to certain types of natural
systems and do those systems exhibit clear hallmarks of intelligence? I fully
grant that intelligent design has its work cut out for it, and that the
requisite analysis is only now beginning. But instead encouraging a fair
scientific assessment of this question, Shermer, Scott, and their supporters do
everything in their power to delegitimize this question so that it cannot
receive a fair hearing within the scientific community. Although intelligent
design is supposed to be weak on predictions, here is one prediction you can
take to the bank: Shermer, Scott, and their supporters will continue to spend
their time manufacturing new forms of red tape aimed at marginalizing
intelligent design rather than admit that intelligent design raises a problem
of genuine scientific merit.
Why are critics of
intelligent design so quick to conflate it with theology -- and a disreputable
form of theology at that? Darwinists like Kenneth Miller and Robert Pennock,
who write full-length books on intelligent design, lament that intelligent
design is theology masquerading science. To this theologians like John Haught
and Ian Barbour add that intelligent design doesn't even succeed as theology?
Why is that? The problem isn't that intelligent design doesn't raise legitimate
topics for scientific research. To reiterate, the central question that
intelligent design raises for science is this: Are there natural systems that
are in principle incapable of being explained in terms of natural causes and do
such systems exhibit features that in any other circumstance we would attribute
to intelligence? This is a legitimate scientific question. Moreover, it's
answer cannot be decided on philosophical or ideological grounds, but must be
decided through careful scientific investigation. Nonetheless, critics of
intelligent design remain adamant that intelligent design is a misbegotten form
of theology.
A little reflection
shows why this is the case. Indeed, why does Kenneth Miller write a book titled
_Finding Darwin's God_ and why does John Haught write a book titled _God after
Darwin_? The juxtaposition here of God and Darwin is not coincidental. I submit
that the preoccupation by critics of intelligent design with theology results
not from intelligent design being inherently theological. Instead, it results
from critics having built their own theology (or anti-theology as the case may
be) on a foundation of Darwinism. Moreover, because intelligent design
challenges that foundation, critics reflexively assume that intelligent design
must be inherently theological and have a theological agenda. Freud, if it were
not for his own virulent Darwinism, would have instantly seen this as a
projection. Critics of intelligent design resort to a classic defense mechanism
in which they project onto intelligent design the very thing that intelligent
design is unmasking in their own views, namely, the extent to which Darwinism,
especially as it has been taken up by today's intellectual elite, has itself
become a project in theology (or anti-theology as the case may be).
Consider Ian
Barbour, for instance. Barbour claims that intelligent design is a form of
natural theology, a designation that in today's science-religion dialogue
guarantees it second-class status. The brahmins of the "science-religion
biz" know better than to engage in natural theology, which they leave to
the pariahs like me. But what is Barbour's alternative to natural theology? He
writes: "My own approach is not natural theology but a theology of nature
in which one asks how nature as understood by science is related to the divine
as understood from the religious experience of a historical community." In
offering a theology of nature rather than natural theology, Barbour appropriates
the intellectual high-ground. But what does that high-ground entail? Indeed,
why in an address to the American Academy of Religion does Barbour need to
stress that design advocates like Huston Smith "underestimate the weight
of evidence favoring neo-Darwinian theory"? Why in that same talk does he
emphasize that "the scientific account is complete on its own level"
and that "scientists have to assume methodological naturalism, that is,
they seek explanations in terms of natural causes" (thus delimiting the
activity of unembodied intelligences that throughout history have played a
non-negligible role in theological discussions -- notably God)? Why does
Barbour perpetuate the myth that "the God of the gaps has steadily
retreated in the history of modern science," when the history of science
is filled with cases in which scientists thought they had resolved a problem
only to discover they hadn't?
The answer, clearly,
is that Barbour has built his "theology of nature," as he calls it,
on Darwinian theory and the naturalistic philosophy that undergirds it.
Specifically, Barbour presupposes that nature is a complete system of natural
causes and that the Darwinian mechanism is the means by which biological
complexity has emerged within nature. As a consequence, intelligent design
cannot appear to him as anything but a thoroughly theological enterprise. Yet
intelligent design is not a theological enterprise. It only seems like a
theological enterprise because, as a scientific theory that challenges
Darwinism, intelligent design challenges the theological edifice that Barbour
himself has built on Darwinism. To challenge a foundation is to challenge any
edifice built on that foundation. That theological edifice, which Barbour
refers to as a theology of nature, is rightly understood as a natural theology.
To be sure, it is not a natural theology of the classic "isn't it amazing
that ..." variety that the British natural theologians are widely
caricatured as having exemplified (in fact, some of the British natural theologians
were far more subtle that we ordinarily give them credit -- e.g., Robert
Boyle). But the basic impulse behind natural theology is certainly there in Ian
Barbour's work, which is to take the science of the day, baptize it, and use it
to obtain theological mileage.
A lot of theology
and anti-theology has been built on Darwinism (Cornelius Hunter details just
how much in his forthcoming book _Darwin's God_, due out this spring with
Brazos Press). The anti-theology of Richard Dawkins, Daniel Dennett, and
William Provine is well-enough known as not to require comment. But the
positive theology that gets built on Darwinism is worth exploring briefly since
its connection to more traditional theologies is not always clear. In
describing his theology of nature, for instance, Barbour characterizes the
theologian's task as relating "nature as understood by science" with
"the divine as understood from the religious experience of a historical
community." What exactly is "the divine as understood from the
religious experience of a historical community"? Traditional theologies --
whether Jewish, Christian, Muslim, or even Mormon -- take as their basic datum
divine revelation, and see that revelation as encapsulated in inspired and
authoritative texts that have an objective sense and that are binding on
believers.
But divine
revelation is not the decisive factor for Barbour and others who build their
theology on the deliverances of science. Instead, the decisive factor is how
the divine is "understood from the religious experience of a historical
community." Notice that all the emphasis here is on the understanding of
the religious community and not on the divine self-revelation that within
traditional theologies is the reason for those communities arising in the first
place. Ultimately what's decisive for Barbour is how the community as it has
come down to the present day understands its religious experience. Now I don't
mean to suggest that this source of theological reflection is irrelevant in
what I'm calling traditional theology. But in putting the emphasis on our
current understanding of religious experience as opposed to our obligation to
align ourselves with an objective revelation, Barbour opens the door to radical
re-understandings of the divine as the religious experience of the community of
faith evolves. And evolve it has, especially in the light of Darwinism.
Conditioned as its religious experience is by Darwinism, the overwhelming move
these days in science-religion discussions is to universalize evolution as a
principle that applies even to the divine. Thus the unchanging God of
traditional theologies gives way to the evolving God of process theologies.
Thus traditional theism with its strong transcendence gives way to panentheism
with its modified transcendence wherein God is inseparable from and dependent
upon the world.
Let me stress that
I'm not arguing here for the superiority of one approach to theology over
another. My point is simply that Darwinism has radical implications for
theology, and that in challenging Darwinism, intelligent design likewise has
radical implications for theology. This is not to say that intelligent design
is a theological enterprise, any more than Darwinism is a theological
enterprise. Darwinism, conceived as a theory about how biological complexity
has emerged in the history of life, is a scientific theory. Intelligent design,
conceived as a theory about the inherent limitations of natural causes to
generate biological complexity and the need for intelligence to overcome those
limitations, is likewise a scientific theory.
In conclusion, there
is no surprise that intelligent design is as controversial as it is.
Intelligent design highlights a breach between popular culture, which is
largely committed to intelligent design, and high culture, which largely
rejects it in favor of Darwinian naturalism. Our intuitions invariably begin
with design. Only by being suitably educated are we educated out of those
intuitions. Even Michael Shermer admits as much in his book _How We Believe_.
According to a poll of 10,000 people that he commissioned, the overwhelming
reason people believe in God is because of the order and complexity they
observe in the natural world and the evidence these are supposed to provide for
design. The problem to date has been that our common intuitions about design
have been inchoate, pretheoretical, and theological. On the other hand, our
reasons for rejecting design as a result of Darwinism have been well-developed,
extensively advertised, and without apparent theological pre-commitments.
Intelligent design is turning the tables on this disparity by promising to
place those inchoate and pretheoretical intuitions on a firm rational
foundation, and by carefully distinguishing design from theology (and
especially natural theology).
Darwinists, who have
held the intellectual high ground for so long, are understandably reluctant to
relinquish their monopoly over high culture. The question is whether they will
continue to misrepresent intelligent design as a theological enterprise to
artificially insulate their theory from competition, or whether they will take
the moral high ground by opening scientific discussions to the questions
intelligent design raises. Not having a particularly optimistic view of human
nature, I expect Darwinists will continue business as usual, misrepresenting
intelligent design as long as they can get away with it and relinquishing their
monopoly over biological education only once the evidence for intelligent
design becomes overwhelming. My hope for the success of intelligent design
therefore resides not with Darwinists but with a younger generation of scholars
who can dispassionately consider the competing claims of Darwinism and
intelligent design.